doi:

DOI: 10.3724/SP.J.1041.2019.01270

Acta Psychologica Sinica (心理学报) 2019/51:11 PP.1270-1280

Enactive cognition: Theoretical rationale and practical approach


Abstract:
There are different theoretical views in the embodied cognition camp, and there is sometimes even conflict among them. Enactive cognition is a new version of recently developed embodied cognition approaches. It claims that the explanation of human cognitive processes across the board should not make any appeal to internal representational or computational states. According to the traditional computation-representation theory of mind, cognitive processes are mechanistically realized in computational processes of building, storing and manipulating detached and abstract internal representations. This cognitivist paradigm has dominated mainstream cognitive psychology for decades. The key assumptions that characterize this representation-centered theory of mind are including that cognition might be understood as computation over mental representations, and that models of cognition should take into account only the inner states of a cognitive individual. But recently this framework has been challenged and criticized. Out of this challenge and criticism emerged the beginnings to an enactive cognition paradigm. The enactive approach to cognitive science proposed a new set of theoretical assumptions for understanding what cognition is and how it works that aims to break the tight conceptual connection between cognition and representation. It takes as its starting point that cognition must not be understood as a capacity for getting an internal representation of a corresponding external reality, which in turn would provide a foundation for supporting thinking, learning, and problem solving. Instead, cognitive processes are deeply entangled in action. Cognition is thus best understood as "enactive"; that is, as a form of practice itself. From the point view of enactive cognition, cognition comes from bodily action and serves bodily action, that is, cognition is embodied action. The key postulate of enactive Cognition is action-related and action-oriented, with the capacity to generate environmental structure by action. Cognition is thus best understood as "enactive"; that is, as embedded action it comes from bodily action and serves bodily action. At the same time, advocates of enactivism state that despite the emphasis on the function of the organism's action of the mind, the model cannot be equated with behaviorism; action, in contrast to behavior, is purposeful and has a cognitive component. Key aspects of enactive cognition are:(1) perception consists in perceptually guided action and (2) cognitive structures emerge from the recurrent sensorimotor patterns that allow action to be perceptually guided. There are three enactive theories in cognitive science. Autopoietic enactivism emphasizes the deep continuity between life and mind; sensorimotor enactivism focuses on analyzing perceptual consciousness in terms of sensorimotor contingency, and radical enactivism focuses on rejecting representationalism in favour of explanatory strategies that emphasize patterns of embodied interaction. These perspectives on enactive cognition are more informed by phenomenology and pragmatism than were earlier versions of embodied cognition. Therefore, we can say that phenomenology and pragmatism constitute the theoretical origin of enactive cognition. The enactive cognition view is not only theoretically viable, but also supported by substantial experimental evidence demonstrating that cognitive processes can be reinterpreted using this new conceptual framework. The theoretical premises of enactive cognition open up new prospects for improving theoretical research and the practical application of cognitive science in the future.

Key words:enactive cognition,embodied cognition,embodied action,body phenomenology,pragmatism

ReleaseDate:2019-11-12 11:47:58



Adams, F. (2010). Embodied cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 619-628.

Allen, M., & Friston, K. J. (2018). From cognitivism to autopoiesis:towards a computational framework for the embodied mind. Synthese, 195(6), 2459-2482.

Bach-y-Rita, P., Collins, C. C., Saunders, F. A., White, B., & Scadden, L. (1969) Vision substitution by tactile image projection. Nature, 221, 963-964.

Barrett, L. (2019). Enactivism, pragmatism…behaviorism?. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 807-818.

Bechtold, L., Bellebaum, C., Egan, S., Tettamanti, M., & Ghio, M. (2019). The role of experience for abstract concepts:Expertise modulates the electrophysiological correlates of mathematical word processing. Brain and Language, 188, 1-10.

Begg, A. (1999). Enactivism and mathematics education. Merga, 22, 68-75.

Bryon, E., Bishop, J. M., McCloughlin, D., & Kaufman, J. (Eds.). (2019). Embodied cognition, acting and performance. Taylor & Francis.

Casasanto, D. (2009). Embodiment of abstract concepts:Good and bad in right-and left-handers. Journal of Experimental Psychology:General, 138(3), 351-367.

Chemero, A. (2013). Radical embodied cognitive science. Review of General Psychology, 17(2), 145-150.

Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3(4), 357-370.

Dewey, J. (1938). Logic:The theory of inquiry. New York:Holt, Rinehart, & Winston.

di Paolo, E. (2018). The enactive conception of life. The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition, 71-94.

Dominey, P. F., Prescott, T. J., Bohg, J., Engel, A. K., Gallagher, S., Heed, T.,... & Schwartz, A. (2016). Implications of action-oriented paradigm shifts in cognitive science. In Engel, A. K., Friston, K. J., & Kragic, D. (Eds.). The pragmatic turn:Toward action-oriented views in cognitive science (Vol. 18). MIT Press.

Engel, A. K., Friston, K. J., & Kragic, D. (Eds.). (2016). The pragmatic turn:Toward action-oriented views in cognitive science (Vol. 18). MIT Press.

Engel, A. K., Maye, A., Kurthen, M., & König, P. (2013). Where's the action? The pragmatic turn in cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(5), 202-209.

Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions:Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

Gallagher, S. (2019). Precis:Enactivist Interventions. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 803-806.

Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119(2), 593-609.

Glenberg, A. M. (2015). Few believe the world Is flat:How embodiment Is changing the scientific understanding of cognition. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 69(2), 165-171.

Held, R., & Hein, A. (1963). Movement-produced stimulation in the development of visually guided behavior. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 56(5), 872-876.

Hoffmann, M., & Pfeifer, R. (2018). Robots as powerful allies for the study of embodied cognition from the bottom up. The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition, 19.

Hutto, D. D. (2015). REC:revolution effected by clarification. Topoi, 36(3), 377-391.

Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism:Basic minds without content. The MIT Press. Cambridge, Massachusetts.

Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism:Basic minds meet content. MIT Press. Cambridge, Massachusetts.

Johnson, M. (2017). Embodied mind, meaning, and reason:How our bodies give rise to understanding. University of Chicago Press.

Jurgens, A., & Kirchhoff, M. D. (2019). Enactive social cognition:Diachronic constitution & coupled anticipation. Consciousness and Cognition, 70(1), 1-10.

Kiefer, M., & Barsalou, L. W. (2013). Grounding the human conceptual system in Perception, action, and internal states. In Action science:foundations of an emerging discipline. Edited by W. Prinz., M. Beisert., & A. Herwig. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Kiverstein, J. (2018). Extended Cognition. The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition, 19-40.

König, P., Melnik, A., Goeke, C., Gert, A. L., König, S. U., & Kietzmann, T. C. (2018). Embodied cognition. International Conference on Brain-Computer Interface (pp.1-4).

Lebon, F., Ruffino, C., Greenhouse, I., Labruna, L., Ivry, R. B., & Papaxanthis, C. (2018). The neural specificity of movement preparation during actual and imagined movements. Cerebral Cortex, 29(2), 689-700.

Lindgren, R., Tscholl, M., Wang, S., & Johnson, E. (2016). Enhancing learning and engagement through embodied interaction within a mixed reality simulation. Computers & Education, 95, 174-187.

Lobo, L., Travieso, D., Jacobs, D. M., Rodger, M., & Craig, C. M. (2018). Sensory substitution:Using a vibrotactile device to orient and walk to targets. Journal of Experimental Psychology:Applied, 24(1), 108-124.

Löhr, G. (2019). Embodied cognition and abstract concepts:Do concept empiricists leave anything out?. Philosophical Psychology, 32(2), 161-185.

Lozada, M., & Carro, N. (2016). Embodied action improves cognition in children:Evidence from a study based on Piagetian conservation tasks. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 393.

Maiese, M. (2018). Can the mind be embodied, enactive, affective, and extended? Phenomenology & the Cognitive Sciences, 17(2), 343-361.

Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1992). The tree of knowledge:The biological roots of human understanding. Boston, MA:Shambhala

McGann, M., de Jaegher, H., & di Paolo, E. (2013). Enaction and psychology. Review of General Psychology, 17(2), 203-209.

Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962/2011). Phenomenology of perception. Translated by Colin Smith. London:Routledge Press.

Pfeifer, R., Iida, F., & Lungarella, M. (2014). Cognition from the bottom up:on biological inspiration, body morphology, and soft materials. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(8), 404-413.

Reid, D. A., & Mgombelo, J. (2015). Survey of key concepts in enactivist theory and methodology. ZDM Mathematics Education, 47, 171-183.

Ruggiero, M., & Catmur, C. (2018). Mirror neurons and intention understanding:Dissociating the contribution of object type and intention to mirror responses using electromyography. Psychophysiology, 55(7), e13061.

Silverman, D. (2013). Sensorimotor enactivism and temporal experience. Adaptive Behavior, 21(3), 151-158.

Slepian, M. L., & Ambady, N. (2012). Fluid movement and creativity. Journal of Experimental Psychology:General, 141(4), 625-629.

Slepian, M. L., Weisbuch, M., Pauker, K., Bastian, B., & Ambady, N. (2014). Fluid movement and fluid social cognition:Bodily movement influences essentialist thought. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 40(1), 111-120.

Soto-Andrade, J. (2018). Enactive Metaphorising in the Learning of Mathematics. In Invited Lectures from the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education (pp. 619-637). Springer, Cham.

Stefanics, G., Heinzle, J., Horváth, A. A., & Stephan, K. E. (2018). Visual mismatch and predictive coding:A computational single-trial ERP study. Journal of Neuroscience, 38(16), 4020-4030.

Stewart, J. (2019). Afterword:a view from enaction. Language Sciences, 71, 68-73.

Su, D. Q., Zhong, Y., Zeng, H., & Ye, H. S. (2013). Embodied semantic processing of Chinese action idioms:Evidence from fMRI study. Acta Psychologica Sinica, 45(11), 1187-1199.

[苏得权, 钟元, 曾红, 叶浩生. (2013). 汉语动作成语语义理解激活脑区及其具身效应:来自fMRI的证据. 心理学报, 45(11), 1187-1199.]

Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology & the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 407-427.

Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991/2010). The embodied mind:cognitive science and human experience. Translated by Li, H.W. et al., HangZhou:Zhejiang University Press.

[F.瓦雷拉, E.汤普森, E.罗施. (1991/2010). 具身心智:认知科学和人类经验. 李恒威等译, 杭州:浙江大学出版社.]

Ward, D., Silverman, D., & Villalobos, M. (2017). Introduction:The varieties of enactivism. Topoi, 36(3), 365-375.

Wu, J. F. (2015). The philosophical study of cognitive enactivism (Unpublished doctorial dissertation). Shanxi University, Tai Yuan.

[武建峰. (2015). 认知生成主义的哲学研究. 山西大学博士学位论文, 太原].